Search This Blog

Sunday 3 January 2016

THE INTER-SUBJECTIVITY OF THE CONCEPT OF BEAUTY  

                     
1.0.PREAMBLE:
The concept of beauty has constituted one of the principal disturbing issues in the history of Aesthetics. And because there has never been a consensus on the definition of the term, the concept of ‘beauty’ has consequently generated controversies among thinkers. For instance, Pythagoras argued that numbers, proportion and patterns constitute beauty.[1] Plato’s Formism ended up in metaphysical objectivism. For him, ‘Beauty’ resides in the world of Forms, and what we conceive as beautiful are only copies of the ideal Beauty. Moreover, according to Aristotle, beauty is nothing but goodness. Besides, David Hume maintained that beauty lies in our individual perception. As a result of these, it is worthy to note that the peculiar quality called ‘beautiful’ is not the same at all times and for all persons. Nevertheless, the fundamental questions remain: What is beauty? What is the nature of beauty? How can we identify someone who is beautiful? In other words, what makes somebody or a work of art beautiful? Is beauty objective or subjective? If I say that beauty lies in how I conceive of it, from where then did I know that it is beautiful? If I say that beauty is objective, how then do I explain the diversity in the conception of beauty? Following from the above, a philosophical investigation into the concept of beauty will solely occupy the interest of this work.


2.0. CONCEPTUAL CLARIFICATION:
The term ‘beauty’ is an English derivative of the 13th century French word la beauté originally from the Latin bellus meaning “good,” “pretty,” “handsome,” or “charming.” The ancient Greeks used the word kαλός (kalos) which signifies “excellence,” or “proportion of parts” to etymologically designate “beauty.” According to W. Tatarkiewicz, the Greeks used the term kalos for ‘beauty’ because “they were particularly convinced that beauty … consists in an arrangement and proportion of parts.”[2] For C. Putnam, ‘beauty’ is said to be the object of study in aesthetics simply because it is “a quality delighting the sense and [so gives] pleasure to the person perceiving it….”[3]

3.0. THE CONCEPT OF BEAUTY: THE MEANING
Dwelling on what beauty is, W. Owens remarks that “of all the transcendentals, beauty is the most evasive and the most difficult to understand.”[4] M.J. Adler adds that “beauty is, perhaps, not definable in any strict sense of definition.”[5] Nevertheless, there have been many attempts to state with the brevity of definition, what beauty is. As such, beauty has been variously thought to be:

A simple, indefinable property that cannot be defined in terms of any other properties; … a property or set of properties of an object that makes the object capable of producing certain sort of pleasurable experience in any suitable perceiver; … whatever produces a particular sort of pleasurable experience, even though what produces the experience may vary from individual to individual. It is in this last sense that beauty is thought to be in the eye of the beholder.[6]

Again, beauty is “the quality of being pleasing to the sense or to the mind.”[7] It is commonly defined as “a characteristic present in objects, such as nature, art work, and a human person, that provides a perceptual experience … to the observer, through sensory manifestations ….”[8] Thus, beauty usually conveys some level of harmony amongst components of an object.

4.0. NATURE AND PROPERTIES OF BEAUTY:
Concerning the nature of beauty, M.F. Slattery submits that “beauty qualifies both nature and art….”[9] For him, the beauty of an art object originates by human agency of the artist. He goes on to say that beauty “qualifies structure, whether this organizes the relations among physical elements or among relations simply as such….”[10] Beauty is not imposed on matter as form is, instead, it “qualifies form itself.”[11] More so, Slattery tells us that “beauty is both objective and subjective. It inheres in objects and, being distinguishable, can also provide an objective criterion; yet beauty depends for its appearance on the mind, since it is the mind that renders relation actual.”[12] Herbert Dieckmann tenders that “the eye and ear perceive beauty as soon as the object or color, shape, and sound are presented to them.”[13] When this is done, “it arouses subconscious, latent, deep-seated forces or emotions, which cannot be analyzed.”[14] All these notwithstanding, Jerome Stolnitz aptly comments that “any attempt to find the properties common and peculiar to beautiful objects is altogether impossible…. Beautiful is just a general term of approbation.”[15]

5.0. THEORIES OF BEAUTY:
These theories hinge upon the angle from which beauty is perceived. They are five in number: objective, subjective, instrumental, formism, and pleasure theories, but only the major ones will be treated here.

5.1.           Objective Theory:
This theory holds that beauty is outside of a subject’s individual biases, feelings, interpretations, and imaginations. For Crispin Sartwell, the objectivists located beauty “in the beautiful object itself or in the qualities of that object.”[16] And so, any judgment “stating that something is beautiful ultimately refers to an underlying… general quality of beauty.”[17] They argue that “variability does not necessarily disprove objectivism….”[18] Furthermore, the intellectual B. Anetoh, writes that “this theory… maintains that what is beauty is objective because beauty is an objective property... [since beauty] is the character of the item itself; [and] the function of object’s context.”[19] The vanguards of this theory include: Pythagoras, Plato, Aristotle, et cetera.

5.2.           Subjective Theory:
For the subjectivists, the foundation of the conception of beauty lies in the response of our feelings, emotions, or our mind. They argue that the origin of beauty is within us. Subsequently, “the beautiful does not result from the effect of objects upon us, nor does it exist as a quality outside of us.”[20] It is with the above, therefore, that the proverbial aphorism, Beauty is in the eye of the beholder, originating from Margaret Hungerford’s famous novel called Molly Bawn, finds sufficient significance in this subjective theory of beauty. The proponents of this view are: David Hume, Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten, Edmund Burke, and Immanuel Kant. For easy assimilation, let us then see the positions of some of these philosophers.

6.0. BEAUTY: THE CENTRAL POSITIONS OF PHILOSOPHERS
6.1.0.     Philosophers Supporting the Objective Existence of Beauty:
6.1.1.     Pythagoras (ca. 570 - 490 B.C.):
Pythagoras claimed “that beauty consists in a well-defined simple proportion of parts….”[21]  For him, “a man… is beautiful when his proportions are correct.”[22] Thus, convinced that beauty depends on proportions, the Pythagoreans, in a general formula expressed that:

Order and proportion are beautiful and useful…. No art comes about without proportion. All art therefore arises through number…. Generally speaking, every art is a system of perceptions, and a system implies number; one can therefore justly say: things look beautiful by virtue of number.[23]

From this, therefore, C. Putnam, while commenting on Pythagoras, quips that “number … is the touchstone of beauty, for from number flow the ratios that make proportion satisfying; from due proportion comes form, as it dwells both in the thing and in the mind of God.”[24]

6.1.2.     Plato (428 - 348 B.C.):
Plato argued that Forms are the true and real objects of knowledge.[25] And these “forms are eternal patterns of which the objects that we see are only copies.”[26] Thus, a beautiful person is a copy of the ideal Beauty. For Plato, the individual form of beauty partakes in the Absolute Beauty which transcends it. Beauty is “independent of relativities; it reveals the Ideal and the universal. It also has the metaphysical property of reconciling the infinite with the finite.”[27] He articulates that from the admiration of the beauty in a human body “one advances to the inward beauty; from there to the contemplation of the beautiful as it appears in observance… and then to the study of the beautiful itself, so that in the end he comes to know the very essence of beauty.”[28] More still, one sees beauty with the recollection of the true Beauty which one once saw in the world of form before passing into the form of a human being.[29]

6.1.3.     Aristotle (384 - 322 B.C.):
Aristotle argued that “we can never find matter without form or form without matter in nature….”[30] For him, substance is a composite of form and matter. Following from this, Aristotle sometimes mentions beauty “in connection with the moral good….[31] Hence, he saw a relationship between the beautiful and virtue, arguing that virtue aims at the beautiful. Besides, for Aristotle, “things are found beautiful…when they are in the condition in which they ought to be.…”[32] In another instance, Aristotle maintains that “a beautiful object, whether it be a living organism or any whole composed of parts, must not only have an orderly arrangement of parts, but must also be of a certain magnitude; for beauty depends on magnitude and order.”[33]

6.2.0.     Thinkers Promoting the Subjective Existence of Beauty:
6.2.1.     David Hume (1711 - 1776 A.D.):
For Hume, “the starting point of our reflections on Beauty is in our experience of a particular kind of agreeableness.”[34] In defence of this view, he writes that:

Beauty is no quality in things themselves: it exists merely in the mind which contemplates them; and each mind perceives a different beauty. One person may even perceive deformity, where another is sensible of beauty; and every individual ought to acquiesce in his own sentiment, without pretending to regulate those of others.[35]

6.2.2.     IMMANUEL KANT (1724 - 1804 A.D.):
According to Sussan L. Feagin, Kant explained the nature of beauty “by analysing judgments that something is beautiful….”[36] For Kant, a judgment on beauty may refer to an experience of the perceiver, but they are not merely expressions of personal experience. So, the judgment that something is beautiful has universal validity. Kant opines that “such judgments are disinterested - determined … by contemplating the mere appearance of the object. These are judgments about an object’s free beauty, and making them requires using only those mental capacities that all humans have by virtue of their ability to communicate with one another. Hence “the pleasures experienced in response to such beauty can in principle be shared by anyone.”[37] Kant, therefore, says that since all men share the same faculties, it is imperative to transcend the subjectivity of beauty. He holds that albeit for the sake of convenience, it can be treated as objective, “beauty itself is subjective…. [And] if it belongs to the noumenal order … it is unknowable….”[38] He concludes that “beauty does not give us knowledge of things in them [selves].”[39]

7.0. BEAUTY IN ARTS AND HUMAN BEINGS: THE CRITERIA
From historical chronicle, there are variable standards of beauty. Paintings, for instance, show a wide range of different standards for beauty. However, the criteria for deciphering beauty in arts revolve around proportion, harmony, perfection, form, and the idea of a model both in shape and colour. Besides, for human beings, beauty is often based on some combination of inner beauty, which includes factors such as: personality, intelligence, refinement, politeness, charisma, integrity, congruence, elegance, and physical attractiveness. Moreover, people who are relatively young, with smooth skin, well-proportioned bodies, that is, with nice body shape, and regular features, have traditionally been considered the most beautiful throughout history. Therefore, a strong indicator of physical beauty in human beings is proportionality or averageness just as the ancient Greek philosophers put it. As such, when body parts are averaged together to form a composition, people with such composition of body parts are often perceived as more beautiful and attractive.

8.0. A PHILOSOPHICAL EVALUATION OF THE CONCEPT OF BEAUTY:
From the above deliberations, one may observe that beauty has been conceived in different ways by various philosophers, even by all mankind. The ancients like Pythagoras conceive beauty as a product of numbers and proportionality. Plato followed this view up by arguing that what we conceive as beautiful is only a copy of the ideal Beauty in the world of Forms. For Aristotle, beauty and goodness are interrelated. When these arguments were raging on, David Hume interrupted by assigning beauty a place in our individual conceptions. For him, beauty lies in the eye of the beholder. However, a closer critical examination of the concept of beauty reveals that in reality, what is beautiful for you may be ugly for me. Someone considered most beautiful in Nigeria may not be taken as the most beautiful in London. A clear example of this is seen in the criteria used for judging the Miss African Queen Switzerland. The judges stated in their criteria for choosing the most beautiful, that, the contestant:

Must have never married, or had her marriage annulled…. Must be of good moral character and shall not be convicted of any crimes and shall possess talent, poise, personality, intelligence, charm and beauty of face and figure…. [Must agree] that the time, manner and method of judging shall be solely at the discretion of the MISS AFRICAN QUEEN SWITZERLAND Committee and that the decision of the judges will be final. Must be a female at birth whose age shall not be less than eighteen, nor more than twenty-seven years….[40]

From this, one sees that even the criteria for judging the most beautiful during a beauty contest are relative and solely depend on the judges as pointed out above. Thus, for the subjectivists, beauty is relative. But the fundamental question for them is: If they claim that beauty is subjective, how then did they come to know the idea of beauty? To have known that somebody is beautiful or not presupposes the fact that one already has an idea of what is beautiful. Hence, at this juncture, one may say that beauty is objective since idea in itself is universal.

Nonetheless, for the objectivists, beauty is objective because it is perceived without comparison to anything external. However, I wonder the possibility of this! Anyway, judging from the arguments of both the objectivists and subjectivists, it becomes expedient for me to follow C. Sartwell in arguing that beauty is BOTH OBJECTIVE AND SUBJECTIVE for “if beauty is entirely subjective, entirely a matter of individual feeling, then, except for conformity to standards set by the customs of the time and place, no criteria would seem to be available for measuring the taste of individuals.”[41] Again, “if beauty is simply objective - something immediately apparent to observation as are the simple sensible qualities - no special training would seem to be needed for sharpening our perception of it.”[42] Still, “if beauty is entirely subjective - that is, if anything that anyone holds to be or experiences as beautiful is beautiful … then it seems that the word has no meaning, or that we are not communicating anything when we call something beautiful except perhaps an approving personal attitude.”[43]

Furthermore, Kant seemed to have mediated between the subjectivists and objectivists. According him, the experience of beauty is unique in that its judgment is represented as universal, that is, valid for every man, yet at the same time, it is “incognizable by means of any universal concept.”[44] Thus, M.J. Adler presents that “in saying that aesthetic judgments have subjective, not objective, universality, and in holding that the beautiful is the object of a necessary satisfaction, Kant also seems to take the middle position which recognizes the subjectivity of the aesthetic judgment without denying that beauty is somehow an intrinsic property of objects.”[45] In such-wise also, Crispin Sartwell, in his book Six Names of Beauty, attributes beauty neither exclusively to the subject nor to the object, but to the relation between them, and even more widely also to the situation or environment in which they are both embedded....”[46] Hence, beauty emerges in situations in which SUBJECT AND OBJECT are juxtaposed and connected!

Further philosophical examination of the concept of beauty may lead one to quickly pose these questions: What is the relationship between beauty and goodness? Is beauty synonymous with goodness? Can a woman who is beautiful be said to be good? In answer to this, Aristotle and some other ancient thinkers claimed that beauty and goodness are fundamentally identical. But, contrary to this view, beauty and goodness logically differ judging from the reality before us. The reason for this is because some who are beautiful are not good, while some others who are good are ugly. Also, another subtle difference between beauty and goodness is that “goodness relates to the appetite … [whereas] beauty relates to a cognitive power.”[47] In other words, “the beautiful satisfies the apprehension, whereas the good itself, properly speaking, satisfies desire….”[48] This explanation, in a way, proves the dichotomy between beauty and goodness. Another answer that can be given on this dichotomy is gotten from Kant who argues that Beauty in Itself cannot be known. What we see is a mere phenomenon, as such, it deceives. Therefore, not all who are beautiful are good!

Additionally, beauty is often confused with truth. The questions remain: Does beauty refer to the truth? Can one who is beautiful be said to be truthful? According to Joyce Stephen, “truth is not beauty, but the true and the beautiful are akin….”[49] In differentiating between them, she says that “truth is beheld by the intellect which is appeased by the most satisfying relations of the intelligible: [whereas] beauty is beheld by the imagination which is appeased by the most satisfying relations of the sensible.”[50] In other words, truth depends on conformity between what is in the mind and what exists in reality independent of the mind, while beauty depends on fitness of parts.[51] Therefore, not all who are beautiful are truthful!

Going further in our examination of the concept of beauty, Plato argued that beauty is in the world of Forms and that all beautiful things participate in the Ultimate Beauty Itself. Thus, just like Kant, ideal Beauty cannot be known. I solidly disagree with them here because if the ideal Beauty exists in the world of forms and cannot be known, how then did they know that there is an ideal Beauty? Therefore, they did not tell us how we are to know something that is beautiful. The implication of Plato’s and Kantian notion of beauty, hence, culminates in dualism.

9.0. CONCLUSION:
Ab initio, this paper dwelt on the concept of beauty. It did this by first of all clarifying the term ‘beauty.’ From this, it delved into the nature and properties of beauty which gave rise to the theories of beauty. Here, philosophers were divergent in their views. Some supported that beauty is objective while others refuted it. From our examination, nevertheless, it is obvious that every form of subjectivity as regards beauty is consistent with objectivity. Beauty involves both the subject who has a certain attitude and pre-understanding as well as the object of beauty. Therefore, I stand on the note that beauty is neither exclusively objective nor is it exclusively subjective since every ascription of beauty to a thing (subjectivity) presupposes that there is something about the thing which makes it beautiful (objectivity). So, all beautiful things share some elements of subjectivity and objectivity in common, and a thing or a person appears to differ in beauty only in terms of degree.

















ENDNOTES:





[1] J.I. Omoregbe, A Simplified History of Western Philosophy, Vol. One (Ikeja: Joja Educational Research and Publishers Limited, 1991; repr. 2011), p. 9.
[2] W. Tatarkiewicz: “Form in the History of Aesthetics,” in P. P. Wiener (Editor-in-Chief), Dictionary of the History of Ideas, Vol II (United States of America & Canada: Charles Scriber’s Sons, 1973), pp. 216-217.
[3] C. Putnam: “Beauty,” in W.J. McDonald (Editor-in-Chief), New Catholic Encyclopedia, Vol. II (New York…Sydney: McGraw-Hill Book Company, 1967), p. 202.
[4] J. Owens, An Elementary Christian Metaphysics (Mikwauukee: The Bruce Publishing Company, 1963), p.122.
[5] M.J. Adler: “Beauty,” in M.J. Adler (Editor-in-Chief), Great Books of the Western World, Vol. I (Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica Inc., 1952), p. 89.
[6] S.L. Feagin: “Beauty,” in R. Audi (ed.), The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, 2nd ed. (United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press, 1995), p. 66 (bold & italics are mine, as emphasis).
[7] A.S. Hornby, Oxford Advanced Learner’s Dictionary, 7th ed. (New York: Oxford University Press, 2006), p. 116.
[8] New World Encyclopedia Contributors: “Beauty” (January 2013). http://www.newworldencyclopedia.org/entry/Beauty   (access 02.12.2015). (bold is mine, as emphasis).
[9] M.F. Slattery: “Beauty in Aesthetics,” in W.J. McDonald (Editor-in-Chief), op.cit., p. 208.
[10] Ibid.
[11] Ibid.
[12] Ibid.
[13] H. Dieckmann: “Theories of Beauty to the Mid-Nineteenth Century,” in P.P. Wiener (Editor-in-Chief), Dictionary of the History of Ideas, Vol. I (United States of America & Canada: Charles Scriber’s Sons, 1973), p. 206.
[14] Ibid.
[15] J. Stolnitz: “Beauty,” in P. Edwards (ed.), The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol. I (New York: The Macmillan Company and The Free Press, 1967), p. 265 (bold & italics are mine, as emphasis).
[16] C. Sartwell: “Beauty” (September 2012). http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/beauty/  (access 02.12.2015).
[17] H. Dieckmann: “Theories of Beauty to the Mid-Nineteenth Century,” in P.P. Wiener (Editor-in-Chief), op.cit., p. 196.
[18] M.C. Beardsley: “Theories of Beauty Since the Mid-Nineteenth Century,” in P.P. Wiener (Editor-in-Chief), op.cit., p. 211.
[19] B. Anetoh, Aesthetics (Unpublished Lecture Note, Dept. of Philosophy, Pope John Paul II Major Seminary, Okpuno-Awka, 2015), p. 3.
[20] H. Dieckmann: “Theories of Beauty to the Mid-Nineteenth Century,” in P.P. Wiener (Editor-in-Chief), op.cit., p. 203.
[21] W. Tatarkiewicz: “Form in the History of Aesthetics,” in P. P. Wiener (Editor-in-Chief), op.cit., p. 217.
[22] Ibid. (bold is mine, as emphasis).
[23] Ibid.
[24] C. Putnam: “Beauty,” in W.J. McDonald (Editor-in-Chief), op.cit. p. 203.
[25] W.F. Lawhead, The Voyage of Discovery, 2nd ed. (Autralia…United States: Eve Howard, 2002), p.  52.
[26] G.N. Udenabo, Beauty in the Eyes of Reason: Theories of Beauty by Modern Philosophers (Unpublished Bachelor’s Thesis, Dept. of Philosophy, Pope John Paul II Major Seminary, Okpuno-Awka, 2007), p. 24.
[27] H. Dieckmann: “Theories of Beauty to the Mid-Nineteenth Century,” in P.P. Wiener (Editor-in-Chief), op.cit., p. 196.
[28] Ibid., p. 205.
[29] Ibid.
[30] S.E. Stumpf, Philosophy: History and Problems, 5th ed. (United States of America: McGraw-Hill, Inc., 1994), p. 91.
[31] Aristotle, Metaphysics, 1078a 31-33, in R. McKeon (ed.), The Basic Works of Aristotle (United States: Modern Library, 2001), p. 893.
[32] C. Putnam: “Beauty,” in W.J. McDonald (Editor-in-Chief), loc.cit.
[33] Aristotle, Theory of Poetry and Fine Art, transl. by S.H. Butcher in S. Rosen (ed.), The Philosopher’s Handbook (New York: Random House Inc., 2003), p. 225.
[34] G.N. Udenabo, op.cit., p. 49.
[35] D. Hume, Essays Moral, Political and Literary, T.H. Green and T.H. Gose (eds.), Vol. II (London, n.p., 1882), p. 1; quoted in G.N. Udenabo, loc.cit. (italics is mine, as emphasis).
[36] S.L. Feagin: “Beauty,” in R. Audi (ed.), op.cit., p. 66.
[37] Ibid.
[38] C. Putnam: “Beauty,” in W.J. McDonald (Editor-in-Chief), op.cit., p. 205.
[39] G.N. Udenabo, op.cit., p. 54.
[40] E. Osei-Tutu: “Rules & Criteria of the Miss African Queen Switzerland Contest” (2013). http://www.panthers-geneva.com/index.php/en/rules-criteria (access 02.12.2015). (bold is mine, as emphasis).
[41] C. Sartwell, loc.cit. (bold is mine, as emphasis).
[42] M.J. Adler: “Beauty,” in M.J. Adler (Editor-in-Chief), op.cit., p. 91 (italics is mine, as emphasis).
[43] C. Sartwell, loc.cit. (italics is mine, as emphasis).
[44] M.J. Adler: “Beauty,” in M.J. Adler (Editor-in-Chief), loc.cit.
[45] Ibid.
[46] C. Sartwell, loc.cit.
[47] C. Putnam: “Beauty,” in W.J. McDonald (Editor-in-Chief), op.cit., p. 204 (bold is mine, as emphasis).
[48] T. Aquinas, Summa Theologica, 1.1.3.3.1.-1.2; in W.J. McDonald (Editor-in-Chief), op.cit., p. 203.
[49] M.J. Adler: “Beauty,” in M.J. Adler (Editor-in-Chief), op.cit., p. 90.
[50] Ibid.
[51] M.F. Slattery: “Beauty in Aesthetics,” in W.J. McDonald (Editor-in-Chief), loc.cit.

BIBLIOGRAPHY:
ADLER, M.J. (Editor-in-Chief),       Great Books of the Western World, Vol. I. Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica Inc., 1952.
ANETOH, B.,                                     Aesthetics. (Unpublished Lecture Note, Dept. of Philosophy, Pope John Paul II Major Seminary, Okpuno-Awka, 2015).
AUDI, R. (ed.),                                   The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, 2nd ed. United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press, 1995, 66-66.
EDWARDS, P. (ed.),                         The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol. I. New York: The Macmillan Company and The Free Press, 1967, 263-266.
HORNBY, A.S.,                                 Oxford Advanced Learner’s Dictionary, 7th ed. New York: Oxford University Press, 2006.
LAWHEAD, W.F.,                             The Voyage of Discovery, 2nd ed. United States: Eve Howard, 2002.
MCDONALD, W.J. (Editor-in-Chief),      New Catholic Encyclopedia, Vol. II. New York…Sydney: McGraw-Hill Book Company, 1967, 202-208.
MCKEON, R. (ed.),                           The Basic Works of Aristotle. United States: Modern Library, 2001.
NEW WORLD ENCYCLOPEDIA CONTRIBUTORS:         “Beauty” (January 2013). http://www.newworldencyclopedia.org/entry/Beauty   (access 02.12.2015).
OMOREGBE, J.I.,                            A Simplified History of Western Philosophy, Vol. One. Ikeja: Joja Educational Research and Publishers Limited, 1991; repr. 2011.
OSEI-TUTU, E.:                                “Rules & Criteria of the Miss African Queen Switzerland Contest” (2013). http://www.panthers-geneva.com/index.php/en/rules-criteria (access 02.12.2015).
OWENS, J.,                                        An Elementary Christian Metaphysics. Mikwauukee: The Bruce Publishing Company, 1963.
ROSEN, S. (ed.),                                The Philosopher’s Handbook. New York: Random House Inc., 2003.
SARTWELL, C.:                                “Beauty” (September 2012). http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/beauty/  (access 02.12.2015).
STUMPF, S.E.,                                  Philosophy: History and Problems, 5th ed. United States of America: McGraw-Hill, Inc., 1994.
UDENABO, G.N.,                              Beauty in the Eyes of Reason: Theories of Beauty by Modern Philosophers. (Unpublished Bachelor’s Thesis, Dept. of Philosophy, Pope John Paul II Major Seminary, Okpuno-Awka, 2007).
WIENER, P.P. (Editor-in-Chief),     Dictionary of the History of Ideas, Vol. I. United States of America & Canada: Charles Scriber’s Sons, 1973, 195-214.
                                                            Dictionary of the History of Ideas, Vol II. United States of America & Canada: Charles Scriber’s Sons, 1973, 216-225.



No comments: